Abstract
The assertion that phylogenetic inference algorithms are not authoritarian because results are repeatable, predictable and freely available misses the point that the authority resides in underlying algorithm models that are not cladistic. We show that optimization procedures can group using symplesiomorphy and that optimization is not always equivalent to cladistic argumentation. Because parsimony and Bayesian algorithms can obtain the same answer from the same data set is not evidence that they are Hennigian; examples exist where these methods do not provide the same result from the same data. Using ‘reversals’ as evidence in systematics is problematic because the question, “Reversal to what?” has no straightforward answer. This confusion can be eliminated by recognizing that homologues are the parts of organisms and homologies are the relationships between the parts, and that the latter is a hierarchical concept rather than transformational. We clarify that Hennig’s auxiliary principle pertains to potential synapomorphy, meaning for molecular work that it is the presence of a particular derived nucleotide that is shared in a given position of aligned sequences of two or more taxa that should be considered homologous until proven otherwise, not simply the alignments themselves. We reiterate that not all data are evidence and we specifically reject homoplasy as a source of ‘evidence’ for systematics. We further reject the view that conflict among data should be resolved through methodology. It is the data that should be our primary focus, as it is our attempts to identify and clarify homologues worthy of suggesting relationships (homology) that are primary in systematics.References
Farris, J.S. (1988) Hennig86, version 1.5. Published by the author.
Gauthier, J.A., Kluge, A. & Rowe, T. (1988) Amniote phylogeny and the importance of fossils. Cladistics, 4, 105–209.
Gill, A.C. & Mooi, R.D. (2011) A show of character – a further response to Wiley et al. Zootaxa, 2946, 29–32.
Gill, T. (1872) Arrangement of the families of fishes, or classes Pisces, Marspobranchii, and Leptocardii. Smithsonian Miscellaneous Contributions, 11 (247), i-xlvi, 1–49.
Goloboff, P.A. (1993) NONA, version 1.1. Published by the author.
Goloboff, P.A. & Pol, D. (2002) Semi-strict supertrees. Cladistics, 18, 514–525.
Goloboff, P.A., Farris, J.S., Källersjö, M., Oxelman, B., Ramírez, M.J. & Szumik, C.A. (2003) Improvements to resampling measures of group support. Cladistics, 19, 324–332.
Hennig, W. (1966) Phylogenetic Systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, Illinois, 263 pp.
Källersjö, M., Albert, V.A. & Farris, J.S. (1999) Homoplasy increases phylogenetic structure. Cladistics, 15, 91–93.
Kluge, A.G. (1976) Phylogenetic relationships in the lizard family Pygopodidae: An evaluation of theory, methods and data. Miscellaneous Publications of the Zoological Museum, University of Michigan, 152, 1–72.
Lankester, E.R. (1870) On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Annals and Magazine of Natural History, Series 4, 6, 34–43.
Mooi, R.D. & Gill, A.C. (2010a) Phylogenies without synapomorphies – a crisis in fish systematics: time to show some character. Zootaxa, 2450, 26–40.
Mooi, R.D. & Gill, A.C. (2010b) A transitioning state or harmful mutation in systematic ichthyology? A reply to Chakrabarty. Copeia, 2010, 516–519.
Mooi, R.D. & Gill, A.C. (2011) Why we shouldn’t let sleeping dogmas lie: a partial reply to Craig. Zootaxa, 2946, 41–44.
Morrison, D.A. (2009) Why would phylogeneticists ignore computerized sequence alignment? Systematic Biology, 58, 150–158.
Naylor, G.J.P. & Adams, D.C. (2003) Total evidence versus relevant evidence: a response to O’Leary et al. (2003). Systematic Biology, 52, 864–865.
Nelson, G.J. (1994) Homology and systematics. In: Hall, B.K. (Ed.). Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative Biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp. 101–149.
Nelson, G. (1996) Nullius in Verba. Published by the author, New York. (Reprinted in Journal of Comparative Biology, 1, 141–156.)
Nelson, G. (2004) Cladistics: Its arrested development. In: Williams, D.M. & Forey, P.L. (eds.). Milestones in Systematics. The 28 · Zootaxa 2946 © 2011 MOOI ET AL. Magnolia Press Systematics Association Special Volume Series 67. CRC Press, London, pp. 127–147.
Nelson, G.J. (2011) Resemblance as evidence of ancestry. Zootaxa, 2946, 137–141.
Nelson, G.J. & Platnick, N.I. (1981) Systematics and Biogeography: Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 567.
Platnick, N.I. (1989) Cladistic and phylogenetic analysis today. In: Fernholm, B., Bremer, K. & Jornvall, H. (eds.). The Hierarchy of Life: Molecules and Morphology in Phylogenetic Analysis. Proceedings from Nobel Symposium 70 held at Alfred Nobel’s Björkborn, Karlskoga, Sweden, August 29-September 2, 1988. Nobel Symposium (70th: 1988: Björkborn, Karlskoga, Sweden), Amsterdam, Oxford: Excerpta Medica, Amsterdam.
Platnick, N.I., Humphries, C.J., Nelson, G.J. & Williams, D.M. (1996) Is Farris optimization perfect? Cladistics, 12, 243–252.
Smith, W.L. & Craig, M.T. (2007) Casting the percomorph net widely: the importance of broad taxonomic sampling in the search for the placement of serranid and percid fishes. Copeia, 2007, 35–55.
Smith, W.L. & Wheeler, W.C. (2004) Polyphyly of the mail-cheeked fishes (Teleostei: Scorpaeniformes): evidence from mitochondrial and nuclear sequence data. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, 32, 627–646.
Sneath, P.H.A. & Sokal, R.R. (1973) Numerical Taxonomy: The Principles and Practice of Numerical Classification. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, 573 pp.
Wiley, E.O. (2008) Homology, identity and transformation. In: Arratia, G., Schultze, H.-P. & Wilson, M.V.H.(eds.). Mesozoic Fishes 4: Homology And Phylogeny. Verlag Dr Friedrich Pfeil, Munich, Germany, pp. 9–21.
Wiley, E.O., Chakrabarty, P., Craig, M.T., Davis, M.P., Holcroft, N.I., Mayden, R.L. & Smith, W.L. (2011) Will the real phylogeneticists please stand up? Zootaxa, 2946, 7–16.
Williams, D.M. (2007) Whatever happened to cladistics? The Systematist, 28, 19–21.
Williams, D.M. & Ebach, M.C. (2010) Perspective: Molecular systematics and the ‘blender of optimization’: Is there a crisis in systematics? Systematics and Biodiversity, 8, 481–484.