Abstract
The formal structure of the inference of a phylogenetic hypothesis is analyzed in the context of the different classes of reasoning applied in all fields of science. Rather than making the traditional distinction between deductive and inductive reasoning, it is shown that phylogenetic hypotheses are derived from a form of non-deductive inference commonly known as abduction. In making distinctions between abductive, deductive, and inductive inferences, the relationships between the origins of hypotheses and their testing become apparent. Abduction serves to provide explanatory hypotheses as tentative answers to specifiable causal questions. It is by way of deduction that specific potential test consequences are determined, whereas induction sensu stricto characterizes the act of carrying out a particular test. The formal structure of phylogenetic inference as a form of abduction is presented. Significant implications arise in recognizing that phylogenetic hypotheses are the products of abductive inference. The most apparent of these are that the distinctions between parsimony and likelihood as methodological criteria are unfounded. Parsimony refers to the relation between a causal question(s) and the hypothesis that serves as an answer for that question(s), whereas likelihood refers to the relation between the evidence as premises and the hypothesis allowed by those premises. The consequence is that parsimony has logical priority over likelihood in abduction, such that the likelihood of any hypothesis is maximized in the event that a causal theory of descent with modification is applied as fully as possible to observed shared similarities. In contrast, the application of rate-dependent theories, under the guise of maximum likelihood, are at odds with observations of shared similarities among two or more species and the causal questions regarding such observations; any rate-dependent theory only pertains to effects that are only tokogenetic in scope, not phylogenetic (sensu Hennig 1966). In recognizing phylogenetic hypotheses as answers to causal questions, the popular conception of testing such hypotheses by the introduction of new characters is incorrect. New character distributions cannot be deduced from a cladogram since such a structure only has causal relevance to the characters for which the hypothesis was inferred. The proper testing of a phylogenetic hypothesis requires the deduction of specific consequences as closely related as possible to the specified causal events of character origins and fixation, and subsequent speciation events. Such consequences must be effects that are independent of the class of effects the hypothesis was intended to explain, i.e., character data. As a result, effects that stand as legitimate potential test evidence are those effects that best support the different sets of causal events presented in the hypothesis. Problems with the popular applications of support indices, as offered by the bootstrap, jackknife, and permutation tests, are discussed. The main problem with these techniques is that they are only useful for testing statistical hypotheses, not explanatory hypotheses. Similarly, Bremer support analysis cannot provide indications of clade support because it is empirically meaningless to compare cladograms of different length, as each hypothesis only has relevance to the respective observations it explains.
References
Abouheif, E. (1997) Developmental genetics and homology: a hierarchical approach. Trends in Evolution and Ecology, 12, 405–408.
Archibald, J.K., Mort, M.E., & Crawford, D.J. (2003) Bayesian inference of phylogeny: a non-technical primer. Taxon, 52, 187–191.
Audi, R. (1998) Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. Routledge, New York, New York, 340 pp.
Ballard, J.W.O., Thayer, M.K., Newton, Jr., A.F., & Grismer, E.R. (1998) Data sets, partitions, and characters: philosophies and procedures for analyzing multiple data sets. Systematic Biology, 47, 367–396.
Bell, J.A. (1994) Reconstructing Prehistory: Scientific Method in Archaeology. Temple University Press, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, 354 pp.
Bininda-Emonds, O.R.P., Gittleman, J.L., & Steel, M.A. (2002) The (super) tree of life: procedures, problems, and prospects. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 33, 265–289.
Bininda-Emonds, O.R.P. (Ed.) (2004) Phylogenetic Supertrees: Combining Information to Reveal the Tree of Life. Computational Biology Series, Volume 4, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, Massachusetts, 550 pp.
Bock, W.J. (1969) The concept of homology. Annals of the New York Academy of Science, 167, 1–73.
Bock, W.J. (1973) Philosophical foundations of classical evolutionary classification. Systematic Zoology, 22, 375–392.
Borror, D.J. (1970) Dictionary of Word Roots and Combining Forms. National Press Books, Palo Alto, California, 134 pp.
Brady, R.H. (1985) On the independence of systematics. Cladistics, 1, 113–126.
Brady, R.H. (1994) Pattern description, process explanation, and the history of morphological sciences. In: Grande, L. & Rieppel, O. (Eds.), Interpreting the Hierarchy of Nature: From Systematic Patterns to Evolutionary Process Theories. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 7–31.
Braithwaite, R.B. (1955) Scientific Explanation: A Study of the Function of Theory, Probability and Law in Science. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 376 pp.
Bremer, K. (1988) The limits of amino acid sequence data in angiosperm phylogenetic reconstruction. Evolution, 42, 795–803.
Bremer, K. (1994) Branch support and tree stability. Cladistics, 10, 295–304.
Brent, J. (1998) Charles Sanders Peirce: A Life. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 412 pp.
Brower, A.V.Z. (2000) Evolution is not a necessary assumption of cladistics. Cladistics, 16, 143–154.
Brower, A.V.Z. & Schawaroch, V. (1996) Three steps of homology assessment. Cladistics, 12, 265–272.
Brown, R.W. (1956) Composition of Scientific Words. Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, D.C., 882 pp.
Bryant, H.N. (1989) An evaluation of cladistic and character analysis as hypothetico-deductive procedures, and the consequences for character weighting. Systematic Zoology, 38, 214–227.
Bull, J.J., Huelsenbeck, J.P., Cunningham, C.W., Swofford, D.L., & Waddell, P.J. (1993) Partitioning and combining data in phylogenetic analysis. Systematic Biology, 42, 384–397.
Bunge, M. (1998a) Philosophy of Science, Volume 1, From Problem to Theory. Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, New Jersey, 605 pp.
Bunge, M. (1998b) Philosophy of Science, Volume 2, From Explanation to Justification. Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, New Jersey, 423 pp.
Camin, J.H. & Sokal, R.R. (1965) A method for deducing branching sequences in phylogeny. Evolution, 19, 311–326.
Carnap, R. (1951) Logical Foundations of Probability. University of Chicago Press, Illinois, 607 pp.
Caws, P. (1965) The Philosophy of Science: A Systematic Account. D. van Nostrand Company, New York, New York, 354 pp.
Charniak E. & McDermott, D. (1985) Introduction to Artificial Intelligence. Addison-Wesley, Massachusetts, 701 pp.
Cleland, C.E. (2001) Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method. Geology, 29, 987–990.
Cleland, C.E. (2002) Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 474–496.
Cohen, M.R., & Nagel, E. (1937) An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method. Harcourt, Brace and Company, New York, New York, 467 pp.
Copi, I.M. & Cohen, C. (1998) Introduction to Logic. Prentice-Hall, Upper Saddle River, New Jersey, 714 pp.
Cracraft, J. & Helm-Bychowski, K. (1991) Parsimony and phylogenetic inference using DNA sequences: some methodological strategies. In: Miyamoto, M.M. & Cracraft, J. (Eds.), Phylogenetic Analysis of DNA Sequences. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, pp. 184–220.
Crother, B.I. (2002) Is Karl Popper”s philosophy of science all things to all people? Cladistics, 18, 445.
Davis, J.I. (1995) A phylogenetic structure for the monocotyledons, as inferred from chloroplast DNA restriction site variation, and a comparison of measures of clade support. Systematic Botany, 20, 503–527.
De Queiroz, K. & Poe, S. (2001) Philosophy and phylogenetic inference: a comparison of likelihood and parsimony methods in the context of Karl Popper”s writings on corroboration. Systematic Biology, 50, 305–321.
De Queiroz, K. & Poe, S. (2003) Failed refutations: further comments on parsimony and likelihood methods and their relationship to Popper”s degree of corroboration. Systematic Biology, 52, 352–367.
Donoghue, M.J. (1992) Homology. In: Fox-Keller, E. & Lloyd, E.A. (Eds.), Key Words in Evolutionary Biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 170–179.
Earman, J. & Salmon, W.C. (1992) Chapter two. The confirmation of scientific hypotheses. In: Salmon, M.H., Earman, J., Glamour, C., Lennox, J.G., Machamer, P., McGuire, J.E., Norton, J.D., Salmon, W.C. & Schaffner, K.F. (Eds.), Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, pp. 42–103.
Eernisse, D. & Kluge, A.G. (1993) Taxonomic congruence versus total evidence, and amniote phylogeny inferred from fossils, molecules, and morphology. Molecular Biology and Evolution, 10, 1170–1195.
Efron, B. (1979) Bootstrap methods: another look at the jackknife. Annals of Statistics, 7, 1–26.
Efron, B. & Tibshirani, R.J. (1993) An Introduction to the Bootstrap. Chapman & Hall, New York, New York, 436 pp.
Efron, B., Halloran, E., & Holmes, S. (1996) Bootstrap confidence levels for phylogenetic trees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 93, 7085–7090.
Eldredge, N. & Cracraft, J. (1980) Phylogenetic Patterns and the Evolutionary Process: Method and Theory in Comparative Biology. Columbia University Press, New York, New York, 349.
Faith, D.P. (2004) From species to supertrees: Popperian corroboration and some current controversies in systematics. Australian Systematic Botany, 17, 1–16.
Faith, D.P. & Cranston, P.S. (1991) Could a cladogram this short have arisen by chance alone?: on permutation tests for cladistic structure. Cladistics, 7, 1–28
Faith, D.P. & Trueman, J.W.H. (1998) When the topology-dependent permutation test (T-PTP) for a null hypothesis of non-monophyly returns significant support for monophyly, should that be equated with (a) rejecting a null hypothesis, (b) rejecting a null hypothesis of “no structure”, (c) failing to falsify a hypothesis of monophyly, or (d) none of the above? Systematic Biology, 45, 577–584.
Faith, D.P. & Trueman, J.W.H. (2001) Towards an inclusive philosophy for phylogenetic inference. Systematic Biology, 50, 331–350.
Fann, K.T. (1970) Peirce”s Theory of Abduction. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, The Netherlands, 62 pp.
Farris, J.S. (1970) Methods for computing Wagner trees. Systematic Zoology, 19, 83–92.
Farris, J.S. (1983) The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis. In: Platnick, N.I. & Funk, V.A. (Eds.), Advances in Cladistics, Volume 2. Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 7–36.
Farris, J.S., Albert, V.A., Källersjö, M., Lipscomb, D. & Kluge, A.G. (1996) Parsimony jackknifing outperforms neighbor-joining. Cladistics, 12, 99–124.
Farris, J.S., Kluge, A.G., & Carpenter, J.M. (2001) Popper and likelihood versus “Popper*.” Systematic Biology, 50, 438–444.
Farris, J.S., Kluge, A.G. & Eckardt, M.J. (1970) A numerical approach to phylogenetic systematics. Systematic Zoology, 19, 172–189.
Felsenstein, J. (1985) Confidence limits on phylogenies: an approach using the bootstrap. Evolution, 39, 783–791.
Felsenstein, J. (2004) Inferring Phylogenies. Sinauer Associates, Inc., Sunderland, Massachusetts, 664 pp.
Fetzer, J.H. (1993) Philosophy of Science. Paragon House, New York, New York, 197 pp.
Fetzer, J.H. & Almeder, R.F. (1993) Glossary of Epistemology / Philosophy of Science. Paragon House, New York, New York, 147 pp.
Fitzhugh, K. (2005a) Les bases philosophiques de l'inférence phylogénétique: une vue d'ensemble. In: Deleporte, P. & Lecointre, G. (Eds.), Philosophie de la systématique. Biosystema, 24, 83–105.
Fitzhugh, K. (2005b) The inferential basis of species hypotheses: the solution to defining the term “species.” Marine Ecology, 26, 155–165.
Fitzhugh, K. (in press a) The “requirement of total evidence” and its role in phylogenetic systema-tics. Biology & Philosophy.
Fitzhugh, K. (in press b) The philosophical basis of character coding for the inference of phylogenetic hypotheses. Zoologica Scripta.
Flach, P.A. (1996) Abduction and induction: syllogistic and inferential perspectives. In: Flach, P.A. & Kakas, A. (Eds.), Proceedings of the ECAI”96 Workshop on Abductive and Inductive Reasoning, Budapest, Hungary, 12 August 1996, pp. 31–35. Available from http://www.cs.bris.ac.uk/%7Eflach/ECAI96/papers.html (accessed 5 November 2005).
Foster, M.H. & Martin, M.L. (1966) General introduction. In: Foster, M.H. & Martin, M.L. (Eds.), Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity: Readings in the Philosophy of Inductive Logic. The Odyssey Press, Inc., New York, New York, pp. 1–13.
Gaffney, E.S. (1979) An introduction to the logic of phylogeny reconstruction. In: Cracraft, J. & Eldredge, N. (Eds.), Phylogenetic Analysis and Paleontology. Columbia University Press, New York, New York, pp. 79–111.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003) Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. University of Chicago Press, Illinois, 271 pp.
Gould, S.J. (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1433 pp.
Grandcolas, P., Deleporte, P. & Desutter-Grandcolas, L. (1997) Testing evolutionary processes with phylogenetic patterns: test power and test limitations. In: Grandcolas, P. (Ed.) The Origin of Biodiversity in Insects: Phylogenetic Tests of Evolutionary Scenarios. Mémoire du Museum National d”Histoire Naturelle, 173, 53–71.
Grande, L. (1994) Repeating patterns in nature, predictability, and “impact” in science. In: Grande, L. & Rieppel, O. (Eds.), Interpreting the Hierarchy of Nature: From Systematic Patterns to Evolutionary Process Theories. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 61–84.
Griffiths, G.C.D. (1974) On the foundations of biological systematics. Acta Biotheoretica, 23, 85–313.
Haas, O. & Simpson, G.G. (1946) Analysis of some phylogenetic terms, with attempts at redefinition. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 90, 319–349.
Hacking, I. (2001) An introduction to probability and inductive logic. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 302 pp.
Hanson, N.R. (1958) Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 241 pp.
Harman, G. (1965) The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.
Harré, R. (1970) The Principles of Scientific Thinking. The University of Chicago Press, Illinois, 324 pp.
Hausman, D.M. (1998) Causal Asymmetries. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 300 pp.
Haszprunar, G. (1992) The types of homology and their significance for evolutionary biology and phylogenetics. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 5, 13–24.
Hempel, C.G. (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. The Free Press, New York, New York, 505 pp.
Hempel, C.G. & Oppenheim, P. (1948) Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.
Hennig, W. (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 263 pp.
Hilpinen, R. (2000) Hempel on the problem of induction. In: Fetzer, J.H. (Ed.), Science, Explanation, and Rationality. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, pp. 91–107.
Hillis, D.M. (1987) Molecular versus morphological approaches to systematics. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 18, 23–42.
Hillis, D.M. (1991) Discriminating between phylogenetic signal and random noise in DNA sequences. In: Miyamoto, M.M. & Cracraft, J. (Eds.), Phylogenetic Analysis of DNA Sequences. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, pp. 278–294.
Holland, J.H., Holyoak, H.K, Nisbett, R.E., & Thagard, P.R. (1989) Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning, and Discovery. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 398 pp.
Houser N. and C. Kloesel (Eds.) (1992) The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings. Volume I (1867–1893). Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 399 pp.
Huelsenbeck, J.P., Bull, J.J., & Cunningham, C.W. (1996) Combining data in phylogenetic analysis. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 11, 152–158.
Huelsenbeck, J.P. & Ronquist, F. (2001) MrBayes: bayesian inference of phylogeny. Bioinformatics, 17, 754–755.
Huelsenbeck, J.P., Ronquist, F., Nielsen, R. & Bollback, J.P. (2001) Bayesian inference of phylogeny and its impact on evolutionary biology. Science, 294, 2310–2314.
Jaeger, E.C. (1947) A Source-Book of Biological Names and Terms. Charles C. Thomas, Springfield, Illinois, 256 pp.
Jevons, W.S. (1883) The Principles of Science: A Treatise on Logic and Scientific Method, Macmillan and Company, London, England, 786 pp.
Josephson, J.R. (1994) Conceptual analysis of abduction. In: Josephson, J.R. & Josephson, S.G. (Eds.), Abductive Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, pp. 5–30.
Josephson, J.R. & Josephson, S.G. (Eds.) (1994) Abductive Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 306 pp.
Kitching, I.J., Forey, P.L., Humphries, C.J., & Williams, D.M. (1998) Cladistics: The Theory and Practice of Parsimony Analyses. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 228 pp.
Kluge, A.G. (1984) The relevance of parsimony to phylogenetic inference. In: Duncan, T. & Stuessy, T. (Eds.), Cladistics: Perspectives on the Reconstruction of Evolutionary History. Columbia University Press, New York, New York, pp. 24–38.
Kluge, A.G. (1989) A concern for evidence and a phylogenetic hypothesis of relationships among Epicrates (Boidae, Serpentes). Systematic Zoology, 38, 7–25.
Kluge, A.G. (1997a) Sophisticated falsification and research cycles: consequences for differential character weighting in phylogenetic systematics. Zoologica Scripta, 26, 349–360.
Kluge, A.G. (1997b) Testability and the refutation and corroboration of cladistic hypotheses. Cladistics, 13, 81–96.
Kluge, A.G. (1998) Total evidence or taxonomic congruence: cladistics or consensus classification. Cladistics, 14, 151–158.
Kluge, A.G. (1999) The science of phylogenetic systematics: explanation, prediction, and test. Cladistics, 15, 429–436.
Kluge, A.G. (2001a) Parsimony with and without scientific justification. Cladistics, 17, 199–210.
Kluge, A.G. (2001b) Philosophical conjectures and their refutation. Systematic Biology, 50, 322–330.
Kluge, A.G. (2003) On the deduction of species relationships: a précis. Cladistics, 19, 233–239.
Kluge, A.G. (2004) On total evidence: for the record. Cladistics, 20, 205–207.
Kluge, A. G. & Farris, J. S. (1969) Quantitative phyletics and the evolution of anurans. Systematic Zoology, 18, 1–32
Kluge, A.G. & Wolf, A.J. (1993) Cladistics: what”s in a word? Cladistics, 9, 183–199.
Kneale, W. (1952) Probability and Induction. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 264 pp.
Kneale, W. & Kneale, M. (1964) The Development of Logic. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 761 pp.
Kruijff, G.-J. M. (1997) Concerning the logics of abduction: on integrating abduction and induction. In: Flach, P.A. & Kakas, A.(Eds.), Proceedings of the IJCAI”97 Workshop on Abductive and Induction in AI, Nagoya, Japan, pp. 31–36. Available from http://www.cs.bris.ac.uk/~flach/IJCAI97/papers.html (accessed 5 November 2005).
Kruijff, G.-J. M. (2005) Peirce's late theory of abduction: a comprehensive account. Semiotica, 153, 431–454.
Lankester, E.R. (1870) On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Annals and Magazine of Natural History, 6, 35–43.
Lacey, A.R. (1976) A Dictionary of Philosophy. Routledge, New York, New York, 266 pp.
Lecointre, G. and Deleporte, P. (2005) Total evidence requires exclusion of phylogenetically misleading data. Zoologica Scripta, 34, 101–117.
Lewis, D. (1991) Counterfactual dependence and time”s arrow. In: Jackson, E. (Ed.), Conditionals. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, pp. 46–75.
Lewis, P.O. & Swofford, D.L. (2001) Back to the future: Bayesian inference arrives in phylogenetics. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 16, 600–601.
Lipton, P. (1993) Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge, New York, New York, 194 pp.
Magnani, L. (2001) Abduction, Reason, and Science: Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic, New York, New York, 205 pp.
Mahner, M. & Bunge, M. (1997) Foundations of Biophilosophy. Springer-Verlag, New York, New York, 423 pp.
Mayr, E. (1982) The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 974 pp.
Medawar, P.B. (1969) Induction and intuition in scientific thought. Memoirs of the American Philosophical Society, 75, 1–62.
Mill, J.S. (1874) A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation. Harper & Bros., New York, New York, 659 pp.
Miyamoto, M.M. (1985) Consensus cladograms and general classifications. Cladistics, 1, 186–189.
Nelson, G. & Platnick, N. (1981) Systematics and Biogeography: Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia University Press, New York, New York, 567 pp.
O’Hear, A. (1980) Karl Popper. Routledge & Keegan Paul, Boston, Massachusetts, 219 pp.
O’Hear, A. (1989) An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Clarendon Press, New York, New York, 239 pp.
Owen, R. (1843) Lectures on the Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Invertebrate Animals, Delivered at the Royal College of Surgeons, in 1843. Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans, London, England, 689 pp.
Owen, R. (1846) Report on the archetype and homologies of the vertebrate skeleton. Report on the Meeting of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, 16, 169–340.
Owen, R. (1849) On the Nature of Limbs. A Discourse Delivered on Friday, February 9, at an Evening Meeting of the Royal Institution of Great Britain. John van Voorst, London, England, 119 pp.
Owen, R. (1866) On the Anatomy of Vertebrates. Vol. I. Fishes and Reptiles. Longmans, Green, and Co., London, England, 650 pp.
Page, R.D.M. & Holmes, E.C. (1998) Molecular Evolution: A Phylogenetic Approach. Blackwell Science, Oxford, England, 346 pp.
Panchen, A.L. (1994) Richard Owen and the concept of homology. In: Hall, B.K. (Ed.), Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative Biology. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 21–62.
Patterson, C. (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey, K.A. & Friday, A.E. (Eds.), Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 21–74.
Peirce, C.S. (1878) Illustrations of the logic of science. Sixth paper. — Deduction, induction, and hypothesis. Popular Science Monthly, 13, 470–482.
Peirce, C.S. (1931–1935) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, volumes 1–6. Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P. & Burks, A. (Eds.). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Peirce, C.S. (1958) Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volumes 7–8. Burks, A. (Ed.). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Pinna, M.C.C. de (1991) Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics, 7, 367–394.
Popper, K.R. (1957) The Poverty of Historicism. Routledge, New York, New York, 166 pp.
Popper, K.R. (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Basic Books, Inc., New York, New York, 480 pp.
Popper, K.R. (1968) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. Harper & Row, New York, New York, 417 pp.
Popper, K.R. (1971) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Volume II, The High Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx, and the Aftermath. Princeton University Press, New Jersey, 420 pp.
Popper, K.R. (1983) Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 395 pp.
Popper, K.R. (1992) Realism and the Aim of Science. Routledge, New York, New York, 420 pp.
Psillos, S. (1996) Ampliative reasoning: induction or abduction? In: Flach, P.A. & Kakas, A. (Eds.), Proceedings of the ECAI”96 Workshop on Abductive and Inductive Reasoning, Budapest, Hungary, 12 August 1996, pp. 1–6. Available from http://www.cs.bris.ac.uk/%7Eflach/ECAI96/papers.html (accessed 5 November 2005).
Reichenbach, H. (1938) Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Illinois, 410 pp.
Reichenbach, H. (1951) The Rise of Scientific Philosophy. University of California Press, Berkeley, 333 pp.
Reichenbach, H. (1956) The Direction of Time. University of California Press, Berkeley, 280 pp.
Reilly, F.E. (1970) Charles Peirce”s Theory of Scientific Method. Fordham University Press, New York, New York, 200 pp.
Remington, R.D. & Schork, M.A. (1985) Statistics with Applications to the Biological and Health Sciences. Prentice-Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 415 pp.
Rescher, N. (1970) Scientific Explanation. The Free Press, New York, New York, 242 pp.
Ridley, M. (1993) Evolution. Blackwell Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 670 pp.
Rieppel, O. (1988) Fundamentals of Comparative Biology. Birkhäuser Verlag, Boston, Massachusetts, 202 pp.
Rieppel, O. (1994) Homology, topology, and topology: the history of modern debates. In: Hall, B.K. (Ed.), Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative Biology. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 63–100.
Rieppel, O. & Grande, L. (1994) Summary and comments on systematic pattern and evolutionary process. In: Grande, L. & Rieppel, O. (Eds.), Interpreting the Hierarchy of Nature: From Systematic Patterns to Evolutionary Process Theories. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 227–255.
Rosen, D.E. (1982) Do current theories of evolution satisfy the basic requirements of explanation? Systematic Zoology, 31, 76–85.
Rupke, N.A. (1993) Richard Owen”s vertebrate archetype. Isis, 84, 231–251.
Russell, E.S. (1916) Form and Function: A Contribution to the History of Animal Morphology. University of Chicago Press, Illinois 383 pp.
Salmon, M.H. (1982) Philosophy and Archaeology. Academic Press, New York, New York, 203 pp.
Salmon, M.H. (1995) Introduction to Logic and Critical Thinking. Harcourt Brace College Publishers, Fort Worth, Texas, 471 pp.
Salmon, W.C. (1967) The Foundations of Scientific Inference. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pennsylvania, 157 pp.
Salmon, W.C. (1984a) Logic. Prentice-Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 180 pp.
Salmon, W.C. (1984b) Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton University Press, New Jersey, 305 pp.
Salmon, W.C. (1989) Four decades of scientific explanation. In: Kitcher, P. & Salmon, W.C. (Eds.), Volume XIII, Scientific Explanation. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp. 3–219.
Salmon, W.C. (1998) Causality and Explanation. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 434 pp.
Sanderson, M.J. & Donoghue, M.J. (1996) The relationship between homoplasy and confidence in a phylogenetic tree. In: Sanderson, M.J. & Hufford, L. (Eds.), Homoplasy: The Recurrence of Similarity in Evolution. Academic Press, New York, New York, pp. 67–89.
Schaffner, K.F. (1993) Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. The University of Chicago Press, Illinois, 617 pp.
Schuh, R.T. (2000) Biological Systematics: Principles and Applications, Cornell University Press, New York, New York, 236 pp.
Scriven, M. (1959) Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory. Science, 130, 477–482.
Siddall, M.E. & Kluge, A.G. (1997) Probabilism and phylogenetic inference. Cladistics, 13, 313–336.
Simpson, G.G. (1961) Principles of Animal Taxonomy. Columbia University Press, New York, New York, 247 pp.
Sluys, R. (1996) The notion of homology in current comparative biology. Journal of Zoological Systematics & Evolutionary Research, 34, 145–152.
Sober, E. (1975) Simplicity. Oxford University Press, New York, New York, 189 pp.
Sober, E. (1986) Explanatory presupposition. Australian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 143–149.
Sober, E. (1988a) Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 265 pp.
Sober, E. (1988b) The principle of the common cause. In: Fetzer, J. (Ed.), Probability and Causation: Essays in Honor of Wesley Salmon. Reidel, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, pp. 211–228.
Sober, E. (1994) From a Biological Point of View: Essays in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge University Press, New York, New York, 255 pp.
Sokal, R.R. & Sneath, P.H.A. (1963) Principles of Numerical Taxonomy. W.H. Freeman and Company, San Francisco, California, 359 pp.
Swofford, D.L., Olsen, G.J., Waddell, P.J., & Hillis, D.M. (1996) Phylogenetic inference. In: Hillis, D.M., Moritz, C. & Mable, B.K. (Eds.), Molecular Systematics. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, Massachusetts, pp. 407–514.
Szalay, F.S. & Bock, W.J. (1991) Evolutionary theory and systematics: relationships between process and pattern. Zeitchrift für zoologische Systematik und Evolutionforschungen, 29, 1–39.
Thagard, P. (1988) Computational Philosophy of Science. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 240 pp.
Van Fraassen, B.C. (1990) The Scientific Image. Clarendon Press, Oxford, England, 235 pp.
von Wright, G.H. (1971) Explanation and Understanding. Cornell University Press, New York, 230 pp.
Wagner, G.P. (1989a) The biological homology concept. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 20, 51–69.
Wagner, G.P. (1989b) The origin of morphological characters and the biological basis of homology. Evolution, 43, 1157–1171.
Wagner, P.J. (2000) Phylogenetic analyses and the fossil record: tests and inferences, hypotheses and models. In: Erwin, D.H. & Wing, S.L. (Eds.), Deep Time: Paleobiology's Perspective. Paleobiology Memoir, 26 (Supplement to No. 4), 341–371.
Walton, D. (2004) Abductive Reasoning. The University of Alabama Press, Tuscaloosa, 303 pp.
Wenzel, J.W. (1997) When is a phylogenetic test good enough? In: Grandcolas, P. (Ed.) The Origin of Biodiversity in Insects: Phylogenetic Tests of Evolutionary Scenarios. Mémoire du Museum National d”Histoire Naturelle, 173, 31–45.
Wheeler, Q.D. (2004) Taxonomic triage and the poverty of phylogeny. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series B, 359, 571–583.
Whitehead, A.N. (1925) Science and the Modern World. Macmillan, New York, New York, 296 pp.
Wiley, E.O. (1975) Karl R. Popper, systematics, and classification: a reply to Walter Bock and other evolutionary taxonomists. Systematic Zoology, 24, 233–243.
Wiley, E.O. (1981) Phylogenetics: The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. John Wiley and Sons, New York, New York, 439 pp.